|

On Cognitive Liberty (Part
III)
Richard Glen Boire
In the last
decade, new computer-based methods for storing, searching, and sharing
data about individuals have proliferated. With the popularization and
commercialization of the Internet, the tracking of individuals and their
databodies has become big business, one in which governments increasingly
participate. In a similar vein, optical devices have become smaller and
cheaper, leading to an expansion of government and corporate surveillance
cameras, which continuously monitor an ever-increasing number of private
and public spaces. These technologically-facilitated developments have
revitalized the ongoing debate about privacy. At issue is what form
privacy will take—both as a principle, as well as a legal protection—in
the so-called Information Age.
While it is commonly thought of as a fundamental right,
privacy is not expressly protected by the U.S. Constitution. In the United
States, the law of privacy has developed in a hodge-podge manner, largely
by Supreme Court decisions in which the Court was presented with a
specific factual scenario and determined whether or not a privacy right
existed in that specific instance. This development pattern has led
some legal scholars to declare that rather than an overarching “right to
privacy,” citizens of the United States enjoy only particularized “rights”
to privacy–those that the U.S. Supreme Court has established in various
cases, or that the U.S. Congress has enacted as specific statutory
protections.
The U.S. Supreme Court, for example, has found a
fundamental right to privacy in the following basic areas: (1)
reproduction, (2) marriage, (3) activities inside the home, (4) the right
to refuse medical treatment, and (5) raising children. Similarly, Congress
has passed federal laws or regulations that grant (to a greater or lesser
degree) privacy protection in a host of areas, including the contents of
first-class mail, information concerning which videotapes you rent, and
information about your bank records.
Although these protections were created by particular
court decisions or by specific statutory enactments, they share an
underlying reasoning and common principles, revealing that a general
concept of privacy does indeed exist.
The legal concept of privacy has developed in fits and
starts, often in union with technological developments. Up until the late
1800s, “privacy” was by-and-large limited to providing a remedy when
someone physically interfered with your (private) property or with your
physical body. A hundred years ago, the right to privacy was not much more
than a right to be free from physical battery and a right to repel
invaders from your land. A major development occurred in 1890, when Samuel
Warren and Louis Brandies penned an influential law review article titled
“The Right to Privacy.”1 Warren and Brandies wrote at the
time when portable cameras and audio recording devices were—for the
first time—available to common people, and newspaper reporters
aggressively embraced these new devices. It was the genesis of the
paparazzi.
In their article, Warren and Brandies articulated a
legal principle, based on general concepts of privacy, which would provide
people with protection against reporters’ efforts to publicize personal
information. As Warren and Brandies wrote:
Instantaneous photographs and newspaper enterprises have invaded the
sacred precinct or private and domestic life; and numerous mechanical
devices threaten to make good the [biblical] prediction that “what is
whispered in the closet shall be proclaimed from the housetops.”2
With their focus on the events of their time, Warren
and Brandies sketched out a theory of privacy that was an extension of the
common law protection of (private) property—a new theory designed to
encompass and protect the public disclosure by reporters of private or
personal information. This broader right they succinctly termed “the
right to be let alone.”
Over 100 years later, this basic phrase remains the
touchstone of what is commonly meant by the “right to privacy.”
Cognitive Liberty and the Right to Privacy
Just as Warren and Brandies called for a revisioning of
“privacy” in the then-new age of portable cameras and audio recorders,
as we enter into the third millennium, with ongoing developments in drug
creation, nano-technology, genetic engineering, and mind-machine
interfacing, it is again time to explore the meaning of privacy and the
scope of what is to receive legal protection as “private” in this (post)modern
age. As the U.S. Supreme Court noted in 1910:
Legislation, both statutory and constitutional, is enacted, it is
true, from an experience of evils but its general language should not,
therefore, be necessarily confined to the form that evil had theretofore
taken. Time works changes, brings into existence new conditions and
purposes. Therefore a principle to be vital must be capable of wider
application than the mischief which gave it birth. This is peculiarly
true of Constitutions. They are not ephemeral enactments, designed to
meet passing occasions. They are, to use the words of Chief Justice
Marshall, “designed to approach immortality as nearly as human
institutions can approach it.3
Thus, while the current privacy debate has centered on
new computer surveillance technology with the power to capture and control
more and more data about each of us, it is time for the privacy debate to
acknowledge, and make explicit, that a person’s mind and mental
processes must be protected as private. “[T]he concept of privacy
embodies the ‘moral fact that a person belongs to himself and not others
nor to society as a whole.’”4 Certainly, a person’s
thoughts and thought processes belong to himself or herself, and not to
society, the government, or any other meddlesome external force.
Inasmuch as a right to privacy entails the right to be
let alone, and centers on the interior and intimate aspects of a person’s
life, cognitive freedom and autonomy should become a central touchstone
for how we conceive of, and apply, a modern right to privacy. The areas in
which the Supreme Court or Congress has expressly declared a right to
privacy all center on interior spaces as opposed to exterior spaces, and
serve to strengthen and protect the autonomy of the personal, or
individual self. There is nothing more interior, and nothing more
important and central to individual autonomy than one’s consciousness.
Indeed, without independent consciousness, no sense of self is even
possible.
Despite its self-evident importance to us today, the
idea that a person is entitled to privacy over his or her own thoughts and
thought processes is actually a fairly recent concept. For most of
history, the inner workings of the mind have been perceived as a threat to
the Church-State. Broad expanses of the U.S. legal system are premised on
an Aristotelian-Thomistic world view. Both Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas
viewed God as a “Supreme Being” who exists outside of and
above humankind. In contrast to God, evil was located within the
individual. The concept of privacy that developed under the Aristotelian-Thomistic
belief system was one inherently skeptical of the human interior and
sought to essentially force into private—to shield behind closed doors—such
things as death, birth, and personal hygienic matters. Under the
Aristolian-Thomistic tradition, the privacy protections that did exist
were limited to those that would benefit the community and ultimately
promote the pleasure of God. Privacy, then, to the extent that it exists
under a Aristotelian-Thomistic paradigm is there to serve and promote the
“general will” rather than to advance individual autonomy and
self-actualization.
A Platonic or Buddhist belief system is just one among
a host of other ways to view the world. In these systems of thought (and
many other “religions,” and/or “philosophies”), god(s) exists both
inside and outside of each person. Thus, a person’s interior thoughts
and thought processes are not feared, but are instead cultivated, revered,
and protected.
Today, however, the U.S. prides itself on being a
secular, pluralist country, free from the shackles of a dominating Church
power. As such, it is no longer appropriate to limit the concept of
privacy to centuries-old models; indeed, just as Brandies and Warren did
over a century ago, it is imperative that we continue to update our
concept of privacy to fit current circumstances.
A modern conception of privacy must shed the
long-standing allegiance to a single way of conceiving of Reality, and
recognize that privacy is rooted in furthering human dignity and autonomy,
and in protecting each person’s right to conceive of the world in his or
her own way. Describing the contours of a modern right to privacy,
Robert Ellis Smith, attorney and publisher of the Privacy Journal,
aptly included “a sense of autonomy, a right to develop a unique
personality and living space, and a right to distinguish one’s own
persona from everyone else’s.”5
As noted earlier, the U.S. Supreme Court has a spotty
record with regard to upholding individual privacy. The Court has found a
narrow range of situations in which a protected privacy right exists, and
a host of situations in which it does not. In 1928, for example, the
Supreme Court ruled that the police could tap a person’s telephone so
long as they did not enter the person’s home in order to place the tap.6
Not until 1967 did the Court rule that the content of telephone
conversations was protected as private regardless of whether the line was
tapped from inside or outside of the home.7 In 1984, the
Supreme Court held that people have no legitimate privacy right with
respect to garbage cans that they have placed on the curb for pickup. Such
garbage, held the Court, may be examined by a police officer without any
need to obtain a warrant.8 In 1989, the Court held that the
police did not violate the privacy right of an individual when they flew
over his home in a helicopter and peered through a hole in his roof in a
search for marijuana plants.9 The latter two cases grew out of
the War on (certain) Drugs, but their holdings extend far beyond drug
cases, significantly reducing the right of privacy for all Americans.
In cases raising issues that directly concern the
privacy of a person’s body in the face of government intrusion,
the decisional trend has been more in favor of individual autonomy.
For example, in 1965 the Supreme Court held that the decision of whether
to use birth control was a private issue for married couples (a ruling
later extended to unmarried couples).10 That case involved a
Connecticut law prohibiting the use of “any drug, medicinal article or
instrument for the purpose of preventing conception.” Such a law, held
the Court, infringed upon a constitutionally protected “zone of privacy”
reserved to individuals–the right to make their own decisions about
reproduction. The Court struck down the Connecticut law based on what it
called “the familiar principle, so often applied by this Court, that a
‘governmental purpose to control or prevent activities constitutionally
subject to state regulation may not be achieved by means which sweep
unnecessarily broadly and thereby invade the area of protected freedoms.’”11
In Roe v. Wade, the court held that the “zone
of privacy” encompasses and protects a woman’s decision to terminate
her pregnancy.12
The principles underlying the Supreme Court’s privacy
rulings, especially those invoked in cases concerning an individual’s
right to make decisions about the interior of his or her body, support the
proposition that personal decisions about how to manage one’s interior thought
processes and consciousness fall within a protected zone of
privacy reserved for individuals, and protected against governmental
invasion or usurpation. Just as the Connecticut law that banned all use of
contraceptives was struck down as “unnecessarily broad,” today’s
drug prohibition laws, which outlaw all use of certain plants and
psychoactive chemicals, trespass upon the zone of privacy that protects an
adult’s right to make decisions about how to manage his or her own
consciousness.
Society recognizes cognitive privacy as reasonable.
What goes on exclusively inside a person’s mind has traditionally been a
private affair. The specter of Orwell’s “mind police” is universally
chilling, as is the idea of a government employing mind control or
thought-manipulation techniques on its citizenry. It is, indeed, a
conservative position to state that if freedom is to mean anything, it
must mean that what goes on inside a person’s skull is a private matter
and something which that person—not the government—has the
right to control.
Just about the only time this cognitive privacy
principle is questioned is when it is applied to “drugs.” For example,
in 1968, the U.S. Supreme Court held that “the mere private possession
of obscene matter cannot be made a crime.”13 In this case,
Mr. Stanley was found in possession (in his own home) of some pornographic
films. He was prosecuted under a Georgia law that made possession of “obscene
matter” a crime. The U.S. Supreme Court struck down the Georgia law,
finding that the law violated the First Amendment. The Court distinguished
laws that regulate the public distribution of “obscene material”
from the Georgia law, which unlawfully targeted mere private possession
of such matter. Hidden away in a footnote, however, the Court remarked
that the same reasoning did not apply to drugs:
What we have said in no way infringes upon the power of the State or
Federal Government to make possession of other items, such as narcotics,
firearms, or stolen goods, a crime. Our holding in the present case
turns upon the Georgia statute’s infringement of fundamental liberties
protected by the First and Fourteenth Amendments. No First Amendment
rights are involved in most statutes making mere possession criminal.14
This was non-binding dictum (commentary that is
superfluous to the actual holding in the case). The Supreme Court has
never been squarely presented with the argument that cognitive liberty is
a fundamental right, or that outlawing mere possession or use of
psychoactive drugs infringes on that fundamental right.
Aside from the comment in the footnote, the reasoning
that pervades the Court’s opinion in Stanley supports the
fundamental principle that what goes on inside a person’s head, the
processing and information therein, is entitled to privacy. The Court
emphasized that the Constitution “protects the right to receive
information and ideas,” and that this right holds irrespective of an
idea’s “social worth.”15 The Court also accepted Mr.
Stanley’s argument that he had a constitutional right to control his own
intellect—to determine for himself what to read or watch in the privacy
of his own home:
[Mr. Stanley] is asserting the right to read or observe what he
pleases—the right to satisfy his intellectual and emotional needs in
the privacy of his own home. He is asserting the right to be free from
state inquiry into the contents of his library. Georgia contends that
appellant does not have these rights, that there are certain types of
materials that the individual may not read or even possess. Georgia
justifies this assertion by arguing that the films in the present case
are obscene. But we think that mere categorization of these films as “obscene”
is insufficient justification for such a drastic invasion of personal
liberties guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth Amendments. Whatever
may be the justifications for other statutes regulating obscenity, we do
not think they reach into the privacy of one’s own home. If the First
Amendment means anything, it means that a State has no business telling
a man, sitting alone in his own home, what books he may read or what
films he may watch. Our whole constitutional heritage rebels at the
thought of giving government the power to control men’s minds.16
When Georgia countered that its law was necessary to
protect people from the detrimental effects of obscenity, the U.S. Supreme
Court recoiled, noting that Georgia’s argument was an inappropriate
attempt “to control the moral content of a person’s thoughts… an
action wholly inconsistent with the philosophy of the First Amendment.”17
The government, explained the Court, “cannot constitutionally premise
legislation on the desirability of controlling a person’s private
thoughts.”18
In the end, the Court in Stanley concluded that
the government may regulate obscenity, but “that power simply does not
extend to mere possession by an individual in the privacy of his own home.”19
The same principles ought to apply with regard to
psychoactive drugs that are used by adults in the privacy of their own
homes. If, as Justice Marshall wrote in Stanley, “[o]ur whole
constitutional heritage rebels at the thought of giving government the
power to control men’s minds,” the State has no business telling a man
or woman sitting in his or her own home, what states of consciousness are
acceptable and what states of consciousness are not.
While the U.S. Supreme Court has never considered a
case in which the issue was framed as “cognitive privacy,” several
state courts have examined the issue of whether drug use falls within a
protected privacy right.20 In all but one case, these state
courts have stacked the deck against cognitive privacy, by narrowly
framing the issue as whether or not there is a fundamental right to use drug
x, rather than whether or not there is a fundamental right to control
one’s own consciousness—a fundamental right upon which drug
prohibition laws substantially infringe.
One interesting case was decided in 1975 by the Alaska
Supreme Court. In Ravin v. State,21 the Alaska
Supreme Court held that the possession and use of marijuana within one’s
own home was included within the scope of the privacy protection
guaranteed by the Alaska Constitution. The case centered on Irwin Ravin, a
man arrested and charged with possession of marijuana. Mr. Ravin filed a
motion to dismiss, arguing that Alaska’s laws prohibiting marijuana use
unconstitutionally infringed upon his right to privacy as guaranteed by
both the U.S. and Alaska Constitutions.
The Alaska court examined U.S. Supreme Court precedent
and concluded that the opinions by the high court do not support a privacy
right to possess marijuana, because “the federal right to privacy only
arises in connection with other fundamental rights.” The Alaska court
then went on to examine whether the privacy protection of the Alaska
Constitution protects an adult’s possession of marijuana in his or
her home.22 The court noted that in a previous case,23
it struck down a public school rule that prohibited long hair, finding
that the school’s rule was prohibited by the Alaska Constitution’s
privacy protection. In that case, the Alaska Supreme Court explained that
“the right ‘to be let alone’—including the right to determine one’s
own hairstyle in accordance with individual preferences and without
interference of governmental officials and agents—is a fundamental right
under the constitution of Alaska.”
The court then revealed an anti-marijuana bias, stating
“few would believe they have been deprived of something of critical
importance if deprived of marijuana, though they would if stripped of
control over their personal appearance.” Here, the court was making an
assumption without evidentiary support, and was also incorrectly framing
the issue. Some people consider their marijuana use at least as important
as their choice of hairstyle. Further, the court drew a false comparison:
comparing a broad principle: “to control one’s appearance;” with a
narrower principle: “to smoke marijuana.” The correct analogy would
have been to compare the two actions at the same level of generality;
thus, the right to control one’s outward appearance ought to have
been compared to the right to control one’s inner cognition.
Based on its faulty comparison, the Ravin court
refused to find that marijuana smoking was within the Alaska constitution’s
privacy protection. Instead, the court relied on the well-established
privacy protections surrounding the home. The court explained, “if
there is any area of human activity to which a right to privacy pertains
more than any other, it is the home.”24 The right to privacy
within the home, held the court, “encompass[es] the possession and
ingestion of substances such as marijuana in a purely non-commercial
context in the home, unless the state can [show that outlawing possession
of marijuana in the home is necessary to achieve a legitimate state
interest.]” More specifically, the court noted that the government had
the “burden of showing a close and substantial relationship between the
public welfare and control of ingestion or possession of marijuana in the
home for personal use.”25
Having shifted the burden to the government, the court
then examined whether the government had met its burden. At trial, the
government claimed that the use of marijuana caused a host of health
problems to the marijuana user, including damage to the immune system and
chromosomal structure, extreme panic reactions, long-term psychological
problems, loss of motivation, and occasional violent behavior.
Before addressing these assertions, the Alaska Supreme
Court questioned whether the government has a legitimate interest in “protecting”
a person from him or herself. While the court was able to conceive of some
circumstances in which the government may have a legitimate interest in
protecting a person from him or herself, such government paternalism was
the exception rather than the rule:
...the authority of the state to exert control over the individual
extends only to activities of the individual which affect others or the
public at large as it relates to matters of public health or safety, or
to provide for the general welfare. We believe this tenet to be basic to
a free society. The state cannot impose its own notions of morality,
propriety, or fashion on individuals when the public has no legitimate
interest in the affairs of those individuals. The right of the
individual to do as he pleases is not absolute, of course: it can be
made to yield when it begins to infringe on the rights and welfare of
others.26
Having stressed that the government should not be in
the business of protecting people from themselves, the court nevertheless
examined the government’s claims that marijuana was dangerous to its
users, finding the evidence of serious harm unpersuasive. The court
explained:
It appears that the effects of marijuana on the individual are not
serious enough to justify widespread concern, at least as compared with
the far more dangerous effects of alcohol, barbiturates and
amphetamines.27
Ultimately, the Alaska Supreme Court concluded “no
adequate justification for the state’s intrusion into the citizen’s
right to privacy by its prohibition of possession of marijuana by an adult
for personal consumption in the home has been shown.”28
While the Ravin case was a clear victory for
marijuana users, and for privacy advocates in general, it was more about
the privacy of the home, than about cognitive freedom and privacy.29
As mentioned earlier, the court did not consider whether cognitive liberty
was protected by the United States Constitution or by the Alaska
constitution. Instead, the decision simply underscored the longstanding
and socially accepted principle that a “man’s home is his castle.”
The case has yet to be forcefully made that our minds, as much as our
homes, are a private inward domain entitled to protection against unwanted
governmental intrusions and prohibitions.
Notes
1. L.D. Brandies and S. Warren, “The Right to
Privacy. The Implicit Made Explicit,” in Harvard L.R., 4; (1890)
193-220.
2. Ibid., 82.
3. Weems v. United States (1910) 217 U.S. 349,
373.
4. Thornburgh v. American College of Obstetricians
& Gynecologists (1986) 476 U.S. 747, 777, n. 5 (Stevens, J.,
concurring), quoting Fried, Correspondence, 6 Phil. & Pub. Affairs
(1977) 288-289.
5. Quoted in D. Brin, The Transparent Society
(Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1998) 77.
6. Olmstead v. United States (1928) 227 U.S.
438.
7. Katz v. United States (1967) 389 U.S. 347.
8. California v. Greenwood (1988) 486 U.S. 35.
9. Florida v. Riley (1989) 488 U.S. 445.
10. Griswold v. Connecticut (1965) 381 U.S. 479.
11. Ibid., 485, quoting, NAACP v. Alabama (1964)
377 U.S. 288, 307.
12. Roe v. Wade (1973) 410 U.S. 113.
13. Stanley v. Georgia (1968) 394 U.S. 557, 559.
14. Ibid., 568, fn. 11.
15. Ibid., 564.
16. Ibid., 565.
17. Ibid., 565-566.
18. Ibid., 566.
19. Ibid., 568.
20. State v. Murphy, 570 P.2d 1070, 1073 (Ariz.
1977); Kreisher v. State, 319 A.2d 31, 32 (Del. Super. Ct. 1974); Laird
v. State, 342 So.2d 962, 963 (Fla. 1977); Borras v. State, 229
So.2d 244, 246 (Fla. 1969); Blincoe v. State, 204 S.E.2d 597, 599
(Ga. 1974); State v. Renfro, 542 P.2d 366, 368-69 (Haw. 1975); State
v. Baker, 535 P.2d 1394, 1399 (Haw. 1975); State v. Kincaid,
566 P.2d 763, 765 (Idaho 1977); State v. O’Bryan, 531 P.2d 1193,
1198 (Idaho 1975); NORML v. Scott, 383 N.E.2d 1330, 1332-33 (Ill.
App. Ct. 1978); State v. Chrisman, 364 So.2d 906, 907 (La. 1978); Marcoux
v. Attorney Gen., 375 N.E.2d 688, 691 (Mass. 1978); Commonwealth v.
Leis, 243 N.E.2d 898, 903-04 (Mass. 1969); People v. Alexander,
223 N.W.2d 750, 752 (Mich. App. 1974); State v. Kells, 259 N.W.2d
19, 24 (Neb. 1977); State v. Nugent, 312 A.2d 158, 162 (N.J. Super.
Ct. App. Div. 1973); Miller v. State, 458 S.W.2d 680, 684 (Tex.
Crim. App. 1970); State v. Anderson, 558 P.2d 307, 309 (Wash. Ct.
App. 1976); State ex rel. Scott v. Conaty, 187 S.E.2d 119, 123
(W.Va. 1972).
Some of these cases, as well as others not listed here,
have compelling dissenting opinions in which judges elaborated certain
aspects of cognitive liberty. For example, in State v. Kramer (Hawaii
1972) 493 P.2d 306, a case upholding the defendant’s conviction for
marijuana possession, Justice Levinson filed a dissenting opinion in which
he argued that the experiences generated by the use of marijuana are
mental in nature, and thus among the most personal and private experiences
possible. (Id. at p. 315.)
21. Ravin v. State (1975) 537 P.2d 494.
22. Unlike the U.S. Constitution, the Alaska
constitution expressly provides for a right to privacy. Article I, Sec. 22
of the Alaska constitution states: “The right of the people to privacy
is recognized and shall not be infringed.”
23. Breese v. Smith (Alaska 1972) 501 P.2d 159.
24. Ravin, supra, 537 P.2d at p. 503.
25. Ibid., 504.
26. Ibid., 509.
27. Ibid., 509-510.
28. Ibid., 511.
29. In 1982, the Alaska legislature codified Ravin in
the state’s criminal code by legalizing possession of up to four ounces
of marijuana in a private place. (See 1982 Alaska Sess. Laws 2 ch. 45.) In
1990, Alaska voters adopted a Voter Initiative that amended Alaska
Statutes section 11.71.060 so as to again make possession of marijuana in
a private place illegal. The (state) constitutional validity of this
initiative is dubious because the initiative merely altered the general
Alaska Criminal Code, not the Alaska Constitution itself, upon which Ravin
was based. (See, e.g., State v. McNeil, No. 1KE-93-947 (D.
Alaska Oct. 29, 1993).
|
|

Subscribe to the print version |